Algebraically closed field with characteristics $0$ versus $\mathbb{C}$

If you want statements that are field-theoretic in nature, then a useful contrast is between the algebraically closed field $\overline{\mathbb Q}$ (the algebraic closure of $\mathbb Q$ in $\mathbb C)$ and $\mathbb C$. The former is the smallest algebraically closed field of char. zero, while $\mathbb C$ is huge in comparison.

For example, $\mathbb C$ contains a sequence of elements $x_i$ which are all mutually algebraically independent (in other words, it contains a copy of the field $\mathbb Q(x_1,\ldots,x_n,\ldots)$ of rational functions over $\mathbb Q$ in a countable number of variables), while $\overline{\mathbb Q}$ does not contain even one element that is algebraically independent of $\mathbb Q$.

Added: Note that the above property makes it much easier to prove the Nullstellenstatz over $\mathbb C$ then over $\overline{\mathbb Q}$, for example.


Here is an example of a non-first order statement which is true over $\mathbb{C}$ (and in fact, any uncountable algebraically closed field) but not, say, over $\overline{\mathbb{Q}}$.

Let $k$ be an algebraically closed field. Recall Schur's lemma: if $A$ is a finite-dimensional $k$-algebra, and $V$ an irreducible $A$-module, then $\hom_A(V, V) = k$ consists of scalars. Under certain circumstances, it is possible to extend this to infinite-dimensional algebras. Dixmier's lemma states that if $k$ is uncountable, then if $A$ is a countably dimensional irreducible $A$-module, we have $\hom_A(V, V) = k$. The usual proof of Schur's lemma (which relies on finding an eigenvalue of an endomorphism) breaks down, but we can argue as follows: $\hom_A(V, V)$ is a division ring, and if it contains an element $T \notin k$, there is a (commutative) field $k(T) \subset \hom_A(V, V)$. But $\hom_A(V, V)$ is countably dimensional (since it injects into $\hom_k(v, V)$ for any $v \neq 0$ in $V$, by irreducibility), whereas $k(T)$ is not countably dimensional if $k$ is uncountable. The partial fractions $1/(T - \lambda), \lambda \in k$ are linearly independent.

The essential idea of the proof is that a proper extension of $k$ must be uncountably dimensional. Note that the restriction on $k$ is necessary: otherwise, for instance, we could take the countably-dimensional $\overline{\mathbb{Q}}$-algebra $\overline{\mathbb{Q}}(t)$ and consider it as a simple module over itself. Then $\hom_\overline{\mathbb{Q}}(t)(\overline{\mathbb{Q}}(t), \overline{\mathbb{Q}}(t)) = \overline{\mathbb{Q}}(t)$. So Dixmier's lemma is false without the cardinality hypotheses.

As Matt E observes, the Nullstellensatz is much easier to prove over uncountable fields: the key lemma in the Nullstellensatz, in fact, is the statement that a finitely generated algebra over a field which is itself a field is an algebraic extension. This cardinality argument gives a quick proof of that.


I (too) find the original question quite vague: there are so many differences between $\overline{\mathbb{Q}}$ and $\mathbb{C}$ that I wouldn't know where to begin. What is more interesting is that by model theory the first order theories of these fields agree.

Compare this with the "Lefschetz Principle" in algebraic geometry: if $K_1$ is any algebraically closed field of characteristic zero and infinite absolute transcendence degree, then "algebraic geometry is the same over $K_1$ as it is over $\mathbb{C}$". The statement in quotation marks is not precise but should definitely be construed to mean much more than just equality of the first order theories, as classical algebraic geometers well know (this is the principle behind Weil's universal domains). Model theorists have tried to enunciate the Lefschetz Principle more precisely, although to the best of my knowledge never in a fully definitive way.

With regard to your "Additional comment": for every positive integer $N$ you have written down a first order statement $P(N)$ in the language of fields which Sudbery showed holds true over $\mathbb{C}$ using, in part, convexity arguments. I claim that it follows immediately from the completeness of $\operatorname{ACF}_0$ that for all $N \in \mathbb{Z}^+$, $P(N)$ holds over any algebraically closed field of characteristic zero (even though there is apparently no sensible notion of "convexity" in this context -- i.e., the model theory is actually helping out here!). Further, by Ax's Transfer Principle, for each fixed $N$, there must exist a positive integer $M(N)$ such that for all primes $p \geq M(N)$, the statement $P(N)$ holds over any algebraically closed field of characteristic $p$. You can find (what I hope is) a very detailed, elementary presentation of this transfer principle in $\S 3.5$ of these notes.

Now, let me draw your attention to the following MathSciNet Review:


MR1152642 (92j:11144) Bartocci, Umberto; Vipera, Maria Cristina On the Gauss-Lucas lemma in positive characteristic. (Italian summary) Atti Accad. Naz. Lincei Rend. Cl. Sci. Fis. Mat. Natur. (8) 82 (1988), no. 2, 211–216 (1989).

If $f(x)$ is a nonconstant polynomial with coefficients in the field of complex numbers of degree $n$, then it has at least one root α; for all k in the range μ≤k≤n, where μ is the multiplicity of α, we have f(k)(α)/=0 (such a root is called a "free'' root of f). This is a consequence of the Gauss-Lucas lemma which was proved by A. Sudbery [Bull. London Math. Soc. 5 (1973), 13--17; MR0320288 (47 #8827)]. Sudbery conjectured that this property remains true for polynomials with coefficients in a field of positive characteristic p>n. Bartocci [Atti Accad. Naz. Lincei Rend. Cl. Sci. Fis. Mat. Natur. (8) 56 (1974), no. 6, 856--858; MR0389865 (52 #10695)] proved that this conjecture is false, but true for p>C(n). In this paper it is shown that, if $n<p<2n−2$, then there exist polynomials which do not have free roots at all. (Reviewed by M. Marden)


That is, the part of Sudbery's conjecture that follows immediately from standard model theory was proven (not using model theory, so far as I know) in a paper published one year later. Much later it was shown that the stronger qualitative form of Sudbery's conjecture is very far from being true. (This situation is somewhat similar to what happened with Artin's Conjecture on $p$-adic fields: see $\S 7$ of the same notes.)